Tangents  

Created: 25 Nov 2000 

Copyright © 2000-2001 by owner.
Standard citation procedures apply.
     


Toward a Sane Drug Policy

The first criterion of any fair and effective public policy is that its premises must be based on fact and sound reason.  The second is that the objectives derived from those premises must be realistic, consistent, and beneficial, while posing as few restrictions upon individual liberty as possible.  Where such things as drugs are concerned, a third consideration is that policy must take into account human whims and desires, which, though often at odds with pure reason, are not always necessarily harmful.  At present, United States policy regarding recreational drugs (those taken for sensory effect rather than for therapeutic purposes) fails wretchedly on each count, and consequently in its effect.  Indeed, it is probably fair to say that failure is the only truly consistent feature of U.S. drug policy.  But though current policy is fraught with inconsistency, there is reason to believe that replacement of the current taboo-ridden system with a sound and objective one would not be impossible.

Because the premises of current drug policy are based as often on hysterical prohibitionist myth (as expressed, for example, in the 1920s propaganda film "Reefer Madness") as on scientific fact, its objectives and methods are correspondingly confused and irrational.  For example, while tobacco's unhealthful qualities are warned against by the Surgeon General's office, its cultivation is subsidized by government.  Meanwhile, cannabis and other relatively benign substances[1] are routinely lumped together with dangerous and highly addictive drugs like heroin and crack cocaine.  Consequently, the production of some undeniably harmful substances is rewarded with subsidies, while casual or even medicinal use of marijuana is punishable by imprisonment.  Is it any wonder, then, that many people, having dared to experiment with some supposedly "dangerous" drugs and finding them no more addictive or harmful than legal drugs, come to mistrust authority and subsequently try other substances which turn out to be truly dangerous, even deadly?

The only way this insane situation can be corrected is for drug laws and regulations to be revamped, so that policy no longer conflicts with reality.  In order for this to happen, we must demand a methodical and unbiased evaluation (by scientists, obviously, not by politicians) of each substance's transient and cumulative effects, such as toxicity, addictiveness, hallucinogenesis, pathogenesis, and impairment (or enhancement) of sensory, motor, and mental function.  These must then be weighed against any beneficial effects, whether analgesic, therapeutic, or simply pleasurable.  Only when we have a clear idea of what problems various drugs pose — as well as what effects are not really problems — can we intelligently formulate effective drug policy.

To begin, it makes little sense for government to victimize further those who are already the victims of drug addiction and trafficking.  Therefore, mere chemical dependence should be treated as a medical problem, not a crime, except when related activity of the user (such as assault, robbery, abuse of spouse or children, or driving or using firearms while intoxicated) poses a threat to others.  In other words, drug policy should mirror alcohol policy:  We do not throw people into prison for abuse of a substance, unless they commit crimes under its influence; otherwise, we treat substance addicts medically, as victims of a disorder.  It makes no sense whatever to imprison people if they do not abuse or threaten anyone else.

Next, drugs with only minimal harmful effects should be decriminalized, and any whose negative effects are insignificant or outweighed by benefits should be fully legalized.  Once minor drugs are made legal, their production and distribution can be subject (as is now the case with alcohol and tobacco) to government regulation and inspection, and risk to consumers thereby further reduced.  Moreover, not only would the expense of such government oversight amount to a mere fraction of that now frittered away on chasing, trying, and incarcerating producers and traffickers of "soft" drugs, it could be completely recovered by taxing the sales of those substances.

Not until the problem has been narrowed to truly dangerous drugs should force of law be considered as a solution.  The purpose of law is not to impose arbitrary rules, but to protect society and individuals from activity which is demonstrably harmful or threatening.  To this end, only the production and distribution of unqualifiedly harmful substances, whose use has been shown to cause strong addiction, psychological disorders, significant degradation of health, or the like, should remain criminal offenses.  On the other hand, potentially dangerous substances which have beneficial applications should be legal but regulated, their administration approved and supervised by medical professionals.

A rational drug policy would offer many benefits.  One of these would be an immediate reduction in prison population, once those whose only "offense" has been to puff a little pot have been released from their pointless incarceration and returned to productive life in general society.  Another would be a drastic reduction of revenues to organized crime, which profits heavily from traffic in illicit commodities — even those which are not harmful.  Finally, doing away with the haphazard misclassification of relatively benign substances as "dangerous" and "addictive" would, over time, do much to restore the now battered credibility of government, and hence reduce widespread confusion (particularly among young experimenters) about which drugs pose little threat and which are truly deadly.  (No policy will prevent stupid behavior, but at least a rational policy will not encourage it.)

The separation of myth from reality is no easy task, especially since they have been intertwined for so long.  Nevertheless, it must be undertaken, for the entanglement of fact and fiction represents the very root of our difficulty in clearly identifying and dealing with the drug issue.  Laws serving no demonstrably beneficial purpose both foster disrespect for law and squander public resources, and ought to be stricken from the books.  Penalties which serve neither constructive nor protective ends are themselves detrimental to any society which values liberty and justice, and should be replaced or abolished.  While government's duty to protect the public from harm is clear, there is no justification whatever for its interference with the production and consumption of relatively harmless substances by responsible adults.

We are right to fear the effects of dangerous drugs, both upon ourselves and upon our society.  But we must no longer permit that fear to draw us and our leaders into irrational and emotional reaction, as it has done for most of the twentieth century.  Such insanity not only hopelessly confuses the issue and inflicts additional harm upon those who are already victims, it also wastes the resources of society and imposes undue expense and hardship upon us all.  Instead, our concern should be directed toward rational, constructive action calculated to protect and heal.

The problem is that the crafting of drug policy is currently entrusted to politicians, who are as hopelessly enthralled by old myths as the public they represent.  The only way out of this quandary is to demand that the job of formulating drug policy be taken away from politicians and given to experts who are equipped to deal with the issue objectively: medical researchers.  Only when we have a clear and objective picture of which substances actually cause significant harm and addiction should we call upon government to establish and enforce drug laws — realistic laws based on facts and reason.  Any other kind is not worthy of a nation which prides itself on liberty and justice.

=SAJ=



Footnote

[1] Some readers might argue that one must have used marijuana (cannabis) in order to be a credible authority on the subject, while others might contend that the judgment of anyone who has used the substance is impaired.  For what it is worth, the only recreational drugs which the author has ever used are alcohol (in moderation), caffeine (in moderation),  and tobacco (quit in 1985).  He is therefore personally familiar with at least one form of addiction.  Although he has never used marijuana, he is acquainted with people who have used it for years, yet have never had the slightest inclination to switch to truly "hard" drugs.

(Click footnote number to return to main text.)


 
The original article was a university composition submitted for credit in November 2000.  It has been modified for Internet presentation through adjustment of format and the addition of hyperlinks.