Getting Specific
So far, we’ve been speaking in generalities. We’re now
ready to consider some examples to connect our theorizing to the real
world. Despite that we might already have clear notions—for example,
that honesty is good and that stealing is bad—simply relying on
authority to tell us which actions are always good and which are always
bad isn’t enough in a real world where issues are often complex and
values come into conflict. Today’s world of science, industry, and
democracy has long since replaced institutions of superstition, slavery,
and monarchy, which formed the framework of traditional moralities of
the Bronze and Iron Ages. As we’ll see, a traditional deontological
view of morality exhibited some problems even in past ages, and these
problems multiply as rigid moralities become increasingly out of step
with accumulating knowledge, advancing technology, and social reform.
Assorted virtues
Let’s consider some behaviors commonly
viewed as
virtues. We’ll begin by setting aside existing moral judgments about
them. We’ll then see if we can determine whether these behaviors are
good, bad, or neutral, not according to authority or vague feelings of
conscience, but with respect to our well defined core value of human
well-being—that is, whether behaviors tend to promote the core value or
endanger it, or else have no significant effect on it.
Honesty: As
we’ve already noted, humans are social creatures. Their well-being
depends greatly on the society of which they’re a part. Society tends
to function most efficiently and productively in an atmosphere of
trust—not blind trust, which leads fools to their downfall, but trust
that’s earned and deserved by those who cultivate the habit and
reputation of speaking truthfully and dealing fairly with others, even
when this might be contrary to their own immediate interests. We can
make better choices when we have accurate information at hand, and when
we don’t have to sift through a stack of distortions and lies to find
it. The more accurate and complete the information we have to work
with, the more easily and quickly our problems can be identified and
solved, with less waste and frustration. Fair wages are offered for a
fair day’s work. Fair transactions can be negotiated with a minimum of
red tape. Fair contracts can be drawn without obscure provisions hidden
in fine print and footnotes. Even stress levels are lower when we don’t feel
compelled to second-guess others at every turn.
In a society that doesn’t value honesty, much energy is
devoted to scheming to gain something that one hasn’t actually earned
through productive labor, and to secure what one has legitimately acquired against
the schemes of others. People are confused about what to believe, and
incentive to produce is diminished, for people have no reasonable
expectation of being able to enjoy the full fruits of their own labor,
and whatever measure of enjoyment they do have is diminished by the
necessity of having to be constantly on guard. Thus, we can see that
honesty is generally a good thing that contributes to human well-being.
However, we’d be foolish to treat honesty as if it were an
absolute good, and dishonesty as if it were always an unforgivable
evil. Suppose, for example, that a resident of German-occupied
Amsterdam in the early 1940s is asked by a Nazi officer where any local
Jews are hiding. Even though the resident knows the answer, he feigns
ignorance, or gives a misleading answer, because he knows that the
well-being of many innocent people would be in peril if he were to tell
the truth. But the situation needn’t be this extreme to warrant an
exception to the rule. We might choose to tell our elderly aunt how
nice she looks, even when at her best she resembles a painted corpse.
If we expect that our frank opinion of her appearance would result only
in hurt feelings and no improvement, and if a small lie on that score
wouldn’t damage our reputation for honesty generally, then things might
work out better for all concerned if we allow diplomacy to trump honesty
in this case. So, we’d do well to consider honesty our rule in the vast
majority of cases, but we should be alert for situations in which the
rule ought to be sidestepped in the interest of the greater good. We
could say that discretion is the better part, not only of valor, but
also of social harmony.
Loyalty is
generally good, because it enhances trust and inspires respect, makes
society more stable, and makes it easier for people to act as a unit in
times of crisis. Like trust and respect, loyalty can’t simply be
demanded; it must be earned, both initially and on an ongoing basis.
But many people can be misled into confusing charisma with virtue, and
fear with respect, and may be inclined to feel their loyalty has been
earned when in fact it has only been elicited by charm or threats. Many
charismatic but misguided, incompetent, unscrupulous, or even psychotic
people, and many appealing but incoherent or even fantastic notions,
have enjoyed the fanatically unquestioning loyalty of their followers,
and the results have sometimes been catastrophic on a grand scale.
Alexander the Great, the Roman Empire, Genghis Khan, the Spanish
Inquisition, Napoleon Bonaparte, the Ku Klux Klan, Josef Stalin, Adolf
Hitler, Joseph McCarthy, Mao Zedong, David Koresh, Osama bin Laden. We
need to be cautious as to which people and ideals we choose to lend our
loyalty. We must in each case consider whether our loyalty to someone
or to something is in accord with our core value, reevaluate that
loyalty from time to time in light of new evidence, and be ready to
renounce it if we find it is abused and no longer deserved.
Courage is
the overcoming of the instinct of fear, to act against one’s own
immediate well-being in the hope of advancing the long term well-being,
whether one’s own or others’. Thus, it must be considered in the
context of its overall potential for good. If there’s a good to be
achieved that is clearly worth the risk, then accepting the risk to
achieve the good is what we call courage.
But if the risk outweighs any good that might plausibly be
achieved—for example, bravado and taking dares—then acting on such
shallow motives is not courage, but
plain foolishness. It puts us (and sometimes others) at risk
for no good purpose, and is thus in conflict with the promotion of
well-being. Failure to exhibit courage in time of genuine need can open
us to charges of cowardice; but if we simply decline to take a foolish
dare, this is not cowardice, but clear and purposeful thinking, and
there’s no shame or vice in this. The only shame is the stupidity
of those who can't tell the difference.
We can do the same for other common virtues, such as
ambition, charity (generosity), fidelity, industriousness, modesty,
sobriety, thrift, and tolerance. In many cases, we’ll get similar
results—in general accord with traditional morality, but with clear
exceptions. It shouldn’t surprise us that a rational approach often
reaffirms tradition. After all, for society to have survived for
thousands of years, people had to be making some successful decisions
about ethics—even if they sometimes might have done the right thing for
the wrong reason. In other cases, however, such as faith and piety,
we’d be hard-pressed to identify a clear benefit to human well-being.
That’s because these values apply specifically to religious practice,
and as such have a connection to well-being only in the sense that their
objective is to obtain divine blessing or a happy afterlife; so, these
have meaning only to those who subscribe to belief in such things.
Believers are free to add such behaviors to their personal moral “to do”
lists, but it’s unreasonable to expect people who don’t share such
beliefs to accept these as virtues. Similarly, some religious people
refuse to accept religious tolerance as a virtue, because they view
beliefs and practices different from their own as universally immoral.
And since there are some such people in each of the major religions (and
even among secularists), each wishing to impose their views upon all
others, and each viewing themselves as virtuous and others as consumed
by evil, we see that the situation results in a stand-off. What to do
about it? The only effective solutions would seem to involve either
segregation of intolerant groups, or else imposition of strict civil
codes prohibiting and punishing any form of interaction that would be
harmful to society.
Vices—the seven deadly sins
Now that we’ve examined the likely consequences of a few virtues, let’s
consider some common vices. Christian tradition provides a handy list
of “seven deadly sins:” wrath, greed, sloth, pride, lust, envy, and
gluttony. We can divide these into two groups: behaviors having
distinct consequences of their own—wrath, sloth, pride, and gluttony—and
cravings whose consequences are indirect, and depend on the way we
choose to deal with those cravings—greed, lust, and envy. Within the
first category, we can re-sequence them in ascending order of their
typical social consequences: sloth, gluttony, pride, and wrath.
Sloth is a
sin of omission rather than commission. More carefully defined,
sloth is a failure to employ one’s natural or acquired knowledge and
skills to some beneficial end. The constructive use of knowledge and
skills benefits society, and so by the same reasoning the withholding or
misuse of such knowledge and skills is correspondingly detrimental to society.
Gluttony
still has the general meaning today that the medieval churchmen gave it:
the excessive consumption of food and drink. In medieval times and in
other situations of scarcity, gluttony by some could deplete limited
resources to the point that others would become malnourished or even
starve. Gluttony can also have adverse effects on the glutton himself,
ruining his health or depleting his wealth. When this happens, he
becomes a burden on the rest of society.
Pride—not the
good sort we feel about ourselves when we’ve accomplished something
admirable, but rather the sort that takes the form of arrogance, the
contempt and abuse of others one assumes to be inferior to
oneself—gives rise to a number of social ills. It often manifests itself as
an assumption of unfair privilege, of exemption from the rules that
apply to everyone else. The arrogant person considers common
responsibility beneath his presumed dignity, demands special treatment
at the expense of others, and thus becomes a social parasite, not only
an irritation to, but also a burden on, the rest of society. Such
behavior is an obvious source of social friction, pitting the prideful
one and the rest of society against each other. And if this arrogance
occupies some position of political power, such friction has been known
to provoke rebellion on numerous occasions.
Wrath is a
destructive response to anger, typically expressed as vengeance, as
opposed to justice. Justice is systematic. It identifies a specific
offense, an offender, and a victim. It prescribes a measured
restitution to the victim (or his survivors) and an appropriate penalty
against the offender. In contrast, vengeance often operates blindly.
In citing an offense, it often inflates a relatively minor, perhaps
unintentional or even imagined slight out of all proportion to the
actual event. Even when it has grounds for complaint, vengeance may
fail to identify a particular perpetrator, and instead scapegoat and
retaliate against an entire family or group of innocents. This, of
course, provokes a countermove by the victims of the vengeance, and, if
no one intervenes, the process escalates back and forth, until one or
both sides in the dispute are annihilated, or until the conflict
spreads to the rest of society and consumes it.
The other three so-called deadly sins—greed, envy,
and lust—are cravings. In themselves, cravings do not constitute
actions of material consequence. They're natural urges; they might
be denied, but they can't be avoided. It's what one does about
them that matters morally. Apart from their internal effects on
the minds and emotions of those who experience them, the consequences
of these vices are indirect,
and may be either positive or negative, depending on the choices one
makes in responding to them.
Greed is a
craving to possess more of something than is necessary. Everyone knows
greed is bad—right? But is what everyone knows an accurate view of
reality? Greed is a natural craving to improve our material well-being
by laying in stores of things (especially money or other forms of
wealth, which can be used to acquire other things). The moral problem
is not greed itself, but rather what we do about it. If the urge
prompts us to steal what we want, then the victim of the theft is
harmed; moreover, the cumulative harm of multiple acts of stealing
percolates through society, and correspondingly erodes society’s ability
to benefit us. But if greed prompts us instead to work harder and
longer in order to earn more money to buy what we want, then the
additional production benefits our business and its customers in
addition to pumping up our own paycheck. Or if it prompts us to invest
in business with the aim of earning a profit, our investment enables the
business to make capital improvements that allow it to become both more
productive and more efficient. Greed is a motivator; it can be used for
bad or for good. It’s the driving force underlying the capitalist
free-market system. When greed serves as an incentive to do something
that benefits society, we can hardly call it a vice in any practical
sense, no matter the judgments of archaic tradition. And the same kind
of reasoning applies to the other so-called sins of craving.
Envy is a
variant of greed; it’s a craving for some specific thing that someone
else possesses. It might be a material item, a position of power and
influence, or anything else whose ownership could by some means be
transferred from that person to ourselves. Again, one might try to
steal a material object, or one might try to assassinate someone in
power in the hope of being able to take over his position. Or again,
one might instead work harder to earn the material object (or one like
it), or compete
fairly to win the position of power from the incumbent. Like greed,
envy is neither harmful nor beneficial in itself; whether it leads to
virtue or to vice depends on how we choose to respond to the craving.
Lust is yet
another craving. Some cultures teach that lust is something inherently
dirty and shameful. Yet it’s a natural, instinctive desire that causes
us to perpetuate our species; without lust, we’d generate no offspring,
and thus become extinct. So obviously, lust has some positive effect on
human well-being, and thus it’s unreasonable to categorize it as a vice
in itself. Once again, whether the craving leads to vice or to virtue
depends on the way we choose to satisfy it, and in that deliberate
choice, not in the mere craving, lies the moral issue. Committing rape
obviously harms the victim; adultery could endanger a marriage;
incaution could risk an unwanted pregnancy or the transmission of
disease. On the other hand, sexual intercourse, in private with a
willing, healthy, adult partner, and using whatever precautions are
appropriate, can be a most gratifying experience of sharing intimate
joy, and perhaps of giving rise to a new life. Once again, for the
reasoning person the virtue or vice is not in the craving itself, but in
the choice of response to the craving.
Surely, we can grant that the churchmen who
compiled this list meant well, that they intended to promote a moral
guidance system relevant to their era, yet simple enough to be memorized
by a largely illiterate audience. But in three instances out of seven,
these learned men made the error of confusing natural cravings with the
negative acts to which they sometimes give rise, and chose to ignore the
good that a natural craving produces when responded to in a positive
manner. It would be as if, rather than identifying gluttony as a sin,
they’d laid the blame instead on the craving that leads to it: hunger;
or if they’d vilified ambition instead of arrogant pride. Ironically,
the medieval priesthood prided itself on its use of logic, but often got
it wrong because their aim was more to promote a dogma than to seek
truth. This shows why it’s a good idea for us to apply up-to-date
evidence and disciplined reasoning to ideas that have been around a long
time, especially ideas we’ve traditionally assumed to be true beyond
question. If an idea is indeed true, then it should be able to
withstand critical scrutiny. If it can’t, then we’re better off
revising, replacing, or retiring it. If our true objective is to find
real solutions to real problems, then we’d be unwise to rely on flawed
reasoning and a knowledge base of fiction and myth.
►
Next:
An Example of In-depth Analysis