Evaluations: Validity and Soundness, Strength and Cogency
With the preceding basics under our belts, we're
now ready to consider some specific measures of how logically convincing
an argument is.
Validity An argument is said to be valid
if its conclusion must be true whenever all of its premises are true.
Before 1969, no human had set foot on the moon.
It's before 1969.
So, no human has set foot on the moon.
The foregoing is a valid argument.
Although it's not actually true that it's before 1969, if that premise
were true, then the conclusion would also have to be true in light of
the first premise, whose truth in any case is a matter of historical
record.
An argument whose conclusion does not
necessarily follow when all of its premises are true is said to be
invalid (pronounced ĭn-`vă-lĭd).
George Washington was the first U.S. president.
John Adams was the second U.S. president.
So, Thomas Jefferson was the third U.S. president.
Although all of the three previous statements
happen to be true according to the historical record, the conclusion
does not logically follow from the two premises. Washington's and
Adams's being the first and second U.S. presidents does not logically
lead to Jefferson's being the third. (Notice that neither
Jefferson nor the third presidency is mentioned in either of the two
premises.) Thus, this argument is
invalid.
A third premise, such as...
Thomas Jefferson was one of the first
three U.S. presidents.
...or...
In alphabetical order by last name, the
first three U.S. presidents were John Adams, Thomas Jefferson, and
George Washington.
...would be needed to introduce these other two
terms into the argument, and thus provide the information and logical
linkages to make it valid and lead inescapably to the conclusion.
Soundness
An argument is said to be
sound if both of the
following conditions apply: (1) it is valid (i.e., its conclusion must
be true if all of its premises are true); and (2) all of its
premises are indeed true. An argument that does not meet both of
these conditions is classified as unsound.
Andrew Carnegie is a philanthropist.
Andrew Carnegie is an atheist.
So, it's possible for an atheist to be a philanthropist.
The conclusion of this argument logically
follows when both premises are true, so the argument is valid; and
indeed it happens that both premises are true. Thus, this argument
is sound.
Heifetz plays the Brahms violin concerto
masterfully.
The Brahms violin concerto is being played masterfully.
So, the Brahms violin concerto is being played by Heifetz.
Although the two premises of this argument are
judgments, let's assume that most classical music authorities would
agree that they're both true. Even so, it doesn't follow that
Heifetz must be playing, because there are other violinists besides
Heifetz who also play the Brahms concerto masterfully. Thus, even
though it's still possible that Heifetz might be the performer in this
case, the argument is unsound because it's invalid.
Now let's consider this one:
The inventor of the automobile was German.
Henry Ford was the inventor of the automobile.
So, Henry Ford was German.
The logic in this argument leads fluidly to the
conclusion. However, one of the premises—the second—is false.
Henry Ford (an American) built an automobile in 1893, and in 1908 was first to put
auto manufacturing on a production-line basis. But the
automobile had already been invented in the 1880s by two Germans,
Gottlieb Daimler and Karl
Benz. So, although the argument is valid, the fact that one of its
premises is false renders the argument unsound and casts its conclusion
into doubt.
That an argument is unsound or invalid is not to
say that it's worthless. Although an argument might not be able to
prove an idea true with absolute certainty, it might well show
that an idea has a high probability of being true, and this is often an
acceptable objective. Whereas an argument is either valid or
invalid, relative strength and cogency fill in the the
broad, gray areas of probability.
Strength
An argument is said to be
strong when its conclusion would
more probably be true than false if all of its premises were true. An argument whose
conclusion is not very probable when its premises are true is said to be
weak. Probability is statistically expressed as a
percentage between 0 and 100, with 0 percent being certainly false and
100 percent being certainly true. With respect to logic, fifty
percent is the break-even point, at or below which an argument is
considered weak; i.e., its conclusion is more likely to be false than to
be true,
even when all of its premises are true.
At exactly fifty percent probability, the likelihood of being false and
being true are equal, which is no more convincing than a random coin
toss. Above fifty percent, the odds shift in favor of the
conclusion's being true when all the argument's premises are true, and the
argument becomes strong—but only relatively so, never certainly. The odds and
strength increase as the probability approaches one hundred percent.
What degree of cogency we ought to demand
depends on the situation. A strength of fifty-plus is adequate for many purposes, but most people
would prefer a probability greater than ninety percent when it comes to
gambling something important, such as their jobs or their lives, on the
outcome. Following is an example of an argument whose strength we
might guess at somewhere around eighty percent:
The stock market has always
gained in aggregate
value over any continuous period of twenty years.
So, a long-term investor will make money in the stock market.
This is a strong argument, even though its
conclusion is far from certain for any individual investor.
Investors often make poor decisions, and particular investments can go
belly-up, even in a bull market. But a long-term investor who
makes informed choices, diversifies his portfolio, and keeps a cool head
through both boom and bust alternations will nearly always average a far
higher rate of return than the slot-machine gambler or lottery player.
Compare this argument to another:
Last week Chris won $50 on a one-dollar lottery
ticket.
So, the lottery is a great investment.
The fact remains that
the aggregate payout of a competently run lottery is never greater than
its aggregate intake. The argument ignores all the losing
one-dollar tickets that Chris had bought over the preceding fifty or
more weeks, which, after his recent win, still leave him a dollar or
more in the hole overall. Nor does it take into account the
thousands of other current players, most of whom won nothing in
last week's lottery.
Note that, in this case, the supporting premise is
founded on the single odd instance of a random win, rather than on a
well established statistical record as in the stock-market example.
The chances of coming out ahead in the lottery, while greater than zero,
are significantly less than fifty percent.
That is, the odds are always that the lottery player will lose more than
he wins.
Even if he wins occasionally, it's very unlikely that his overall
losses in a pure-chance game of more-than-two-to-one odds will ever be completely recouped. Thus, the
lottery argument is weak.
Cogency
An argument is said to be
cogent when both of the
following conditions apply: (1) it is strong (i.e., its conclusion is
probably true if all of its premises are true); and (2) all of
its premises are indeed true. An argument that does not meet both
of these conditions is classified as uncogent. As with
strength and weakness, cogency and uncogency are relative terms, not
absolute.
All life forms we've observed are carbon-based.
So, all life forms are carbon-based.
This is a very strong and (so far) cogent argument, since
we've observed millions of life forms, and all without
exception fit the carbon-based pattern. However, we're fairly
sure we haven't yet observed all life forms on earth, and there might
well be life forms elsewhere in the universe, perhaps some of which
might have very different chemistries. For this reason, we can't
be absolutely certain of the argument's conclusion; nonetheless, we can
be very confident that the next terrestrial life form we discover—and fairly
confident that the next hundred or the next thousand—will be
carbon-based.
As we can see, there are parallel relationships
between validity and soundness, and between
strength and cogency. Indeed, there's a
degree of conceptual overlap, since validity and soundness are absolute
extensions of strength and cogency, respectively. However, there
is this difference: A valid argument could also be said to be
strong, and a sound argument could also be said to be cogent.
But a strong or cogent argument cannot be claimed to be valid or sound,
unless the probability that its conclusion is true is fully 100 percent
(i.e., absolutely certain). Any statistical value less than
100 percent reflects only a probability, never a certainty. Whereas a
sound argument's conclusion must be true if all of its premises
are true, there is always some chance that a cogent argument's
conclusion could be false despite that all of its premises are true.
▼