PARTICULAR STATEMENTS
Often, we aren't concerned with all men, or all
mortals, or all of anything else. Sometimes we need to distinguish
some men, some mortals, etc., as being in some way different from other
men, mortals, or whatever. Consider the following two premises:
Socrates is a man.
Socrates is a philosopher.
So... what?
What, if anything, can we conclude from these
two statements? All men are philosophers? No, because
Socrates is only one man among many, and other men might be different
from Socrates in a number of ways, including whether or not they're
philosophers. How about All philosophers are men? No,
we can't conclude that either, because the information given in these
premises doesn't rule out the possibility that non-men (e.g., gods,
women, or even other clever species) might be philosophers, too.
However, conclusions we can legitimately draw from these premises
include the following:
Some man is a philosopher;
or
Some men are philosophers.
In either case, the meaning is this:
Something exists in the category of men which is also in the category of
philosophers. Now, this something might be only one thing (Socrates), or
it might be many things
(Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, Descartes, Leibniz, Hume, Kant,
Wollstonecraft, Nietzsche, Sartre, Russell, and hundreds of others).
Indeed, the conclusion opens the door to the possibility that everything
in the category of men is also in the category of philosophers, unless
some other statement rules this possibility out.
Such a limiting statement might be:
Some man is not a philosopher;
or
Some men are not philosophers.
(As we'll note, the second of these is
equivalent to the colloquial expression, Not all men are philosophers,
which might also be casually (but erroneously) expressed as All men are not
philosophers, which could technically be interpreted No men are
philosophers—obviously something quite different from the original.
This potential ambiguity arising from imprecise use of language is why logicians scrupulously avoid the All
S are not P and Not all S are P constructions, as
should we likewise.)
Now, the only difference between
Some man is not a philosopher and Some men are not philosophers
is that the one is expressed in the singular and the other in the
plural; so far as logic is concerned, there's no difference at all, as
long as no particular number of men is specified, and as long as the
number is greater than zero. Some men implies at least
one man; it can't mean no men. So, let's arbitrarily pick the plural version,
Some men are not philosophers,
and pair it with a corresponding but contrary statement, Some men are
philosophers. Again, we have two statements of the same
general class—this time particular instead of universal—but again, one
statement is negative and the other affirmative. Thus, we now have four
general forms of categorical statements:
Relationship |
|
Structure (Plural) |
|
|
|
Structure (Singular) |
universal |
|
affirmative |
|
All S are
P |
|
or |
|
Every S is
P |
universal |
|
negative |
|
No S are
P |
|
or |
|
No S is
P |
particular |
|
affirmative |
|
Some S are
P |
|
or |
|
At least one S is
P |
particular |
|
negative |
|
Some S are not
P |
|
or |
|
At least one S is not
P |
Each statement form can
be expressed in different ways without changing its overall meaning.
Different ways of expressing the same idea are called
stylistic variants. Some of
the most common variants of each form are listed here.
Relationship |
|
General Structure |
|
Typical Stylistic Variants |
universal affirmative |
|
All S is / are P. |
|
Each / every S is P. |
|
Any S is / are P. |
|
Only P is / are S. |
universal negative |
|
No S is / are P. |
|
Each / every S is not P. |
|
Any S is / are not P. |
|
No P is / are S. |
particular affirmative |
|
Some S is / are P. |
|
At least one S is P. |
|
Something is both S and
P. |
|
Some P is / are S. |
particular negative |
|
Some S is / are not P. |
|
At least one S is not P. |
|
Something is S but not P. |
|
Not all S is / are P. |
(Note that our abstract representations of
statement forms here are somewhat different from the style we used in
the Symbolic Logic section. In the previous section, we used lower
case letters to represent entire statements. In this case, we're
representing individual terms—subject and predicate—within statements,
and the capital letters help to emphasize this distinction.)
▼